Sponsored Links

Minggu, 25 Februari 2018

Sponsored Links

Introduction to Fair Division - YouTube
src: i.ytimg.com

Fair division is the problem of dividing a set of goods or resources between several people who have an entitlement to them, such that each person receives his/her due share. This problem arises in various real-world settings: auctions, divorce settlements, electronic spectrum and frequency allocation, airport traffic management, or exploitation of Earth Observation Satellites. This is an active research area in Mathematics, Economics (especially Social choice theory), Game theory, Dispute resolution, and more. The central tenet of fair division is that such a division should be performed by the players themselves, maybe using a mediator but certainly not an arbiter as only the players really know how they value the goods.

There are many different kinds of fair division problems, depending on the nature of goods to divide, the criteria for fairness, the nature of the players and their preferences, and other criteria for evaluating the quality of the division.

The mathematical fair division problem is an idealization of those real life problems. The theory of fair division provides explicit criteria for various different types of fairness. Its aim is to provide procedures (algorithms) to achieve a fair division, or prove their impossibility, and study the properties of such divisions both in theory and in real life.


Video Fair division



Definitions

There is a set X {\displaystyle X} and a group of n {\displaystyle n} players. A division is a partition of X {\displaystyle X} to n {\displaystyle n} disjoint subsets: X = X 1 ? X 2 ? ? ? X n {\displaystyle X=X_{1}\sqcup X_{2}\sqcup \cdots \sqcup X_{n}} , one subset per player.

What is divided?

The set X {\displaystyle X} can be of several types:

  • X may be a finite set of indivisible items, for example: X = { p i a n o , c a r , a p a r t m e n t } {\displaystyle X=\{piano,car,apartment\}} , such that each item should be given entirely to a single person.
  • X may be an infinite set representing a divisible resource, for example: money, or a cake. Mathematically, a divisible resource is often modeled as a subset of a real space, for example, the section [0,1] may represent a long narrow cake, that has to be cut into parallel pieces. The unit disk may represent an apple pie.

Additionally, the set to be divided may be:

  • homogeneous - such as money, where only the amount matters, or
  • heterogeneous - such as a cake that may have different ingredients, different icings, etc.

Finally, it is common to make some assumptions about whether the items to be divided are:

  • desirable - such as a car or a cake, or
  • undesirable - such as house chores.

The problem of dividing a set of indivisible and heterogeneous items is called fair item assignment.

The problem of dividing a set of divisible and homogeneous items is called fair resource allocation. A special case is fair division of a single homogeneous resource.

The problem of dividing a divisible, heterogeneous and desirable resource is also called fair cake-cutting.

The problem of dividing a set of heterogeneous and undesirable items is also called fair Chore division (if the chores are divisible) or chore assignment (if they are not).

Combinations are also possible, for example:

  • When dividing inheritance, or dividing household property during divorce, it is common to have both desirable indivisible heterogeneous items, desirable divisible heterogeneous property such as land, and desirable divisible homogeneous property such as money.
  • In the housemates problem, several friends rent a house together, and they have to both allocate the rooms in the apartment (a set of indivisible, heterogeneous, desirable goods), and divide the rent to pay (divisible, homogeneous, undesirable good).

What is fair?

Most of what is normally called a fair division is not considered so by the theory because of the use of arbitration. This kind of situation happens quite often with mathematical theories named after real life problems. The decisions in the Talmud on entitlement when an estate is bankrupt reflect some quite complex ideas about fairness, and most people would consider them fair. However they are the result of legal debates by rabbis rather than divisions according to the valuations of the claimants.

According to the Subjective theory of value, there cannot be an objective measure of the value of each item. Therefore, objective fairness is not possible, as different people may assign different values to each item. Empirical experiments on how people define the concept of fairness lead to inconclusive results.

Therefore, most current research on fairness focuses on concepts of subjective fairness. Each of the n {\displaystyle n} people is assumed to have a personal, subjective utility function or value function, V i {\displaystyle V_{i}} , which assigns a numerical value to each subset of X {\displaystyle X} . Usually the functions are assumed to be normalized, so that every person values the empty set as 0 ( V i ( ? ) = 0 {\displaystyle V_{i}(\emptyset )=0} for all i), and the entire set of items as 1 ( V i ( X ) = 1 {\displaystyle V_{i}(X)=1} for all i) if the items are desirable, and -1 if the items are undesirable. Examples are:

  • If X {\displaystyle X} is the set of indivisible items {piano, car, apartment}, then Alice may assign a value of 1/3 to each item, which means that each item is important to her just the same as any other item. Bob may assign the value of 1 to the set {car, apartment}, and the value 0 to all other sets except X; this means that he wants to get only the car and the apartment together; the car alone or the apartment alone, or each of them together with the piano, is worthless to him.
  • If X {\displaystyle X} is a long narrow cake (modeled as the interval [0,1]), then, Alice may assign each subset a value proportional to its length, which means that she wants as much cake as possible, regardless of the icings. Bob may assign value only to subsets of [0.4, 0.6], for example, because this part of the cake contains cherries and Bob only cares about cherries.

Based on these subjective value functions, there are a number of widely used criteria for a fair division. Some of these conflict with each other but often they can be combined. The criteria described here are only for when each player is entitled to the same amount:

  • A proportional division, also called simple fair division, means that every person gets at least his due share according to his own value function. For instance if three people divide up a cake each gets at least a third by their own valuation, i.e. each of the n people gets a subset of X which he values as at least 1/n:
    • V i ( X i ) >= 1 / n {\displaystyle V_{i}(X_{i})\geq 1/n} for all i.
  • An envy-free division guarantees that no-one will want somebody else's share more than their own, i.e. every person gets a share that he values at least as much as all other shares:
    • V i ( X i ) >= V i ( X j ) {\displaystyle V_{i}(X_{i})\geq V_{i}(X_{j})} for all i and j.
  • An exact division is one where all players agree on the value of each share :
    • V i ( X i ) = V j ( X i ) {\displaystyle V_{i}(X_{i})=V_{j}(X_{i})} for all i and j.
  • An equitable division means every person feels exactly the same happiness, i.e. the proportion of the cake a player receives by their own valuation is the same for every player. This is a difficult aim as players need not be truthful if asked their valuation:
    • V i ( X i ) = V j ( X j ) {\displaystyle V_{i}(X_{i})=V_{j}(X_{j})} for all i and j.

When the recipients have different measures of value of the parts of the resource, it is possible to have super fair divisions - divisions in which each person receives strictly more than his due share. For example, in the "cake cutting" version, one recipient may like marzipan, another prefers cherries, and so on. Then, and only then, the n recipients may get even more than what would be one n-th of the value of the "cake" for each of them. On the other hand, the presence of different measures opens a vast potential for many challenging questions and directions of further research.

In addition to fairness, it is sometimes desired that the division be Pareto optimal, i.e., no other allocation would make someone better off without making someone else worse off. The term efficiency comes from the economics idea of the efficient market. A division where one player gets everything is optimal by this definition so on its own this does not guarantee even a fair share.

Note that the criteria of a fair division are stated in terms of a players valuations, their level of entitlement, and the results of a fair division procedure. The valuations of the other players are not involved in the criteria. Differing entitlements can normally be represented by having a different number of proxy players for each player but sometimes the criteria specify something different.

In the real world of course people sometimes have a very accurate idea of how the other players value the goods and they may care very much about it. The case where they have complete knowledge of each other's valuations can be modeled by game theory. Partial knowledge is very hard to model. A major part of the practical side of fair division is the devising and study of procedures that work well despite such partial knowledge or small mistakes.


Maps Fair division



Procedures

A fair division procedure lists actions to be performed by the players in terms of the visible data and their valuations. A valid procedure is one that guarantees a fair division for every player who acts rationally according to their valuation. Where an action depends on a player's valuation the procedure is describing the strategy a rational player will follow. A player may act as if a piece had a different value but must be consistent. For instance if a procedure says the first player cuts the cake in two equal parts then the second player chooses a piece, then the first player cannot claim that the second player got more.

What the players do is:

  • Agree on their criteria for a fair division
  • Select a valid procedure and follow its rules

It is assumed the aim of each player is to maximize the minimum amount they might get, or in other words, to achieve the maximin.

Procedures can be divided into finite and continuous procedures. A finite procedure would for instance only involve one person at a time cutting or marking a cake. Continuous procedures involve things like one player moving a knife and the other saying stop. Another type of continuous procedure involves a person assigning a value to every part of the cake.

Two players

For two people there is a simple solution which is commonly employed. This is the so-called divide and choose method. One person divides the resource into what they believe are equal halves, and the other person chooses the "half" they prefer. Thus, the person making the division has an incentive to divide as fairly as possible: for if they do not, they will likely receive an undesirable portion. This solution guarantees an envy-free division. If the valuations of the players are sigma additive, then an envy-free division is also proportional. The article on divide and choose describes why the procedure is not equitable.

More complex procedures like the adjusted winner procedure are designed to cope with indivisible goods and to be more equitable in a practical context.

Austin's moving-knife procedure gives an exact division for two players. The first player positions a knife over the left side of the cake. The player moves the knife to the right and when either player says to stop, they receive the left piece of cake. This produces an envy-free division.

The surplus procedure (SP) achieves a form of equitability called proportional equitability. This procedure is strategy proof and can be generalized to more than two people.

Many players

Fair division with three or more players is considerably more complex than the two player case.

Proportional division is the easiest and the article describes some procedures which can be applied with any number of players. Finding the minimum number of cuts needed is an interesting mathematical problem.

Envy-free division was first solved for the 3 player case in 1960 independently by John Selfridge of Northern Illinois University and John Horton Conway at Cambridge University. The best algorithm(Selfridge-Conway discrete procedure) uses at most 5 cuts.

The Brams-Taylor procedure was the first cake-cutting procedure for four or more players that produced an envy-free division of cake for any number of persons and was published by Steven Brams and Alan Taylor in 1995. This number of cuts that might be required by this procedure is unbounded. A bounded moving knife procedure for 4 players was found in 1997.

There are no discrete algorithms for an exact division even for two players, a moving knife procedure is the best that can be done. There are no exact division algorithms for 3 or more players but there are 'near exact' algorithms which are also envy-free and can achieve any desired degree of accuracy.

A generalization of the surplus procedure called the equitable procedure (EP) achieves a form of equitability. Equitability and envy-freeness can be incompatible for 3 or more players.

Nonadditive Utility

Most of the existing fair-division procedures outlined above assume players' utility to be additive. In other words, if a player derives a certain amount of utility from 25 g of chocolate cake, then the player is assumed to derive exactly twice as much utility from 50 g of the same chocolate cake.

In 2013, Rishi S. Mirchandani showed that most existing fair-division algorithms are incompatible with nonadditive utility functions. Further, he proved that instances of the fair-division problem in which players have nonadditive utility functions may have no proportional solution.

Mirchandani suggested that the fair-division problem can be solved using techniques of nonlinear optimization. However, it remains as an open question whether there exist more efficient algorithms for specific subsets of nonadditive utility functions.


Fair Division | Brilliant Math & Science Wiki
src: ds055uzetaobb.cloudfront.net


Variants

Some cake-cutting procedures are discrete, whereby players make cuts with a knife (usually in a sequence of steps). Moving-knife procedures, on the other hand, allow continuous movement and can let players call "stop" at any point.

A variant of the fair division problem is chore division: this is the "dual" to the cake-cutting problem in which an undesirable object is to be distributed amongst the players. The canonical example is a set of chores that the players between them must do. Note that "I cut, you choose" works for chore division.

A basic theorem for many person problems is the Rental Harmony Theorem by Francis Su.: Suppose a number of housemates in house with as many bedrooms as housemates seek to decide who gets which room and for what part of the total rent. Also, suppose that the following conditions hold:

  1. Good House: In any partition of the rent, each person finds some room acceptable.
  2. Miserly Tenants: Each person always prefers a free room (one that costs no rent) to a non-free room.
  3. Closed Preference Sets: A person who prefers a room for a convergent sequence of prices prefers that room at the limiting price.

From this, there exists a partition of the rent so that each person prefers a different room. An interesting application of the Rental Harmony Theorem can be found in the international trade theory.

Sperner's Lemma can be used to get as close an approximation as desired to an envy-free solutions for many players. The algorithm gives a fast and practical way of solving some fair division problems.

The division of property, as happens for example in divorce or inheritance, normally contains indivisible items which must be fairly distributed between players, possibly with cash adjustments (such pieces are referred to as atoms).

A common requirement for the division of land is that the pieces be connected, i.e. only whole pieces and not fragments are allowed. For example the division of Berlin after World War 2 resulted in four connected parts.

A consensus halving is where a number of people agree that a resource has been evenly split in two, this is described in exact division.

The special case of fair division of waters flowing in an international river has been studied with some detail; see fair river sharing.

A generalization of the problem is to allow each interested party to consist of several players who share the same set of resources but have different preferences.


Fair Division: The Divider-Chooser Method - YouTube
src: i.ytimg.com


History

According to Sol Garfunkel, the cake-cutting problem had been one of the most important open problems in 20th century mathematics, when the most important variant of the problem was finally solved with the Brams-Taylor procedure by Steven Brams and Alan Taylor in 1995.

Divide and choose's origins are undocumented. The related activities of bargaining and barter are also ancient. Negotiations involving more than two people are also quite common, the Potsdam Conference is a notable recent example.

The theory of fair division dates back only to the end of the second world war. It was devised by a group of Polish mathematicians, Hugo Steinhaus, Bronis?aw Knaster and Stefan Banach, who used to meet in the Scottish Café in Lvov (then in Poland). A proportional (fair division) division for any number of players called 'last-diminisher' was devised in 1944. This was attributed to Banach and Knaster by Steinhaus when he made the problem public for the first time at a meeting of the Econometric Society in Washington D.C. on 17 September 1947. At that meeting he also proposed the problem of finding the smallest number of cuts necessary for such divisions.

Envy-free division was first solved for the 3 player case in 1960 independently by John Selfridge of Northern Illinois University and John Horton Conway at Cambridge University, the algorithm was first published in the 'Mathematical Games' column by Martin Gardner in Scientific American.

Envy-free division for 4 or more players was a difficult open problem of the twentieth century. The first cake-cutting procedure that produced an envy-free division of cake for any number of persons was first published by Steven Brams and Alan Taylor in 1995.

A major advance on equitable division was made in 2006 by Steven J. Brams, Michael A. Jones, and Christian Klamler.


Fair Division: The Lone Divider Method - YouTube
src: i.ytimg.com


In popular culture

  • In Numb3rs season 3 episode "One Hour", Charlie talks about the cake-cutting problem as applied to the amount of money a kidnapper was demanding.
  • Hugo Steinhaus wrote about a number of variants of fair division in his book Mathematical Snapshots. In his book he says a special three-person version of fair division was devised by G. Krochmainy in Berdechów in 1944 and another by Mrs L Kott.
  • Martin Gardner and Ian Stewart have both published books with sections about the problem. Martin Gardner introduced the chore division form of the problem. Ian Stewart has popularized the fair division problem with his articles in Scientific American and New Scientist.
  • A Dinosaur Comics strip is based on the cake-cutting problem.

Fair Division: The Moving Knife Method - YouTube
src: i.ytimg.com


See also


Fair division - YouTube
src: i.ytimg.com


References


Exploring Majors Fair - University of Southern Indiana
src: www.usi.edu


Further reading

  • Brams, Steven J.; Taylor, Alan D. (1996). Fair division: from cake-cutting to dispute resolution. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-55644-9. 
  • Robertson, Jack; Webb, William (1998). Cake-Cutting Algorithms: Be Fair If You Can. Natick, Massachusetts: A. K. Peters. ISBN 1-568-81076-8. 
  • Hill, T.P. (2000). "Mathematical devices for getting a fair share". American Scientist. 88: 325-331. doi:10.1511/2000.4.325. 

Fair Division of One Cake by Two Persons - YouTube
src: i.ytimg.com


External links

  • Fair Division from the Discrete Mathematics Project at the University of Colorado at Boulder.
  • The Fair Division Calculator (Java applet) at Harvey Mudd College
  • Fair Division: Method of Lone Divider
  • Fair Division: Method of Markers
  • Fair Division: Method of Sealed Bids
  • Vincent P. Crawford (1987). "fair division," The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, v. 2, pp. 274-75.
  • Hal Varian (1987). "fairness," The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, v. 2, pp. 275-76.
  • Bryan Skyrms (1996). The Evolution of the Social Contract Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-55583-8

Source of the article : Wikipedia

Comments
0 Comments